Starting from the second half of the twentieth
century, there has been a rising interest, in modern scientific theories, about
the notion of emergence. Its compatibility and explanatory power with theories
that involve the study of complexity and nonlinear systems are expressed in
many recent works in the field of philosophy of science. These works showcase
an ongoing debate about emergence and reductionism, and despite the divergences
of the definitions and the approaches regarding emergence, it is very often
connected with the notions of non-predictability, complexity and contingency.
Focusing on the later one, we will argue about the connection of emergence and
contingency by focusing on three modern scientific theories that make strong
cases for emergence. Starting with Chaos Theory in Mathematics, we have strong
cases of the emergence of physical properties, as a result of non-infinite
precision in calculating a system’s initial conditions. In Evolutionary
Biology, we have the theory of Punctuated Equilibrium and Stephen Gould’s
approach to the occurrence of species extinctions, and in History of Science,
Cushing’s theory for the role of Historical Contingency in theory selection in
science, that showcase the connection between contingency and emergence. Based
on this analysis, we propose the enrichment of the discussion concerning the
Nature of Science (NoS) with the aspects of emergence and contingency embodied in modern scientific theories, highlighting
their contribution to an educational environment that values the NoS.
References
[1]
Alexander, S. (1920). Space, Time, and Deity. Dover Publications.
[2]
Batterman, R. W. (2011). Emergence, Singularities, and Symmetry Breaking. Foundations of Physics, 41, 1031-1050.
[3]
Bedau, M. A. (1997). Mind, Causation, and World, Weak Emergence. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 375-398.
[4]
Bishop, R. C., & Atmanspacher, H. (2006). Contextual Emergence in the Description of Properties. Foundations of Physics, 36, 1753-1777.
[5]
Boon, M. (2015). Contingency and Inevitability in Science—Instruments, Interfaces and the Independent World. In L. Soler, E. Trizio, & A. Pickering (Eds.), Science as It Could Have Been: Discussing the Contingent/Inevitable Aspects of Scientific Practices (pp. 151-174). University of Pittsburgh Press.
[6]
Broad, C. D. (1925). The Mind and Its Place in Nature. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
[7]
Cushing, J. T. (1990). Theory Construction and Selection in Modern Physics—The S Matrix. Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139170123
[8]
Cushing, J. T. (1992). Historical Contingency and Theory Selection in Science. Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 1992, 446-457.
https://doi.org/10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1992.1.192774
[9]
Cushing, J. T. (1994).Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Hegemony. University of Chicago Press
[10]
Cushing, J. T. (2003). Philosophical Concepts in Physics: The Historical Relation between Philosophy and Scientific Theories. Leader Books.
[11]
Duhem, P. (1982). The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (Vol. 126). Princeton University Press.
[12]
Eldredge, N., & Gould S. J. (1972). Punctuated Equilibria: An Alternative to Phyletic Gradualism. In T. J. M. Schopf (Ed.), Models in Paleobiology (pp. 82-115). Freeman, Cooper and Company.
[13]
Gontier, N. (2015). Uniting Micro- with Macroevolution into an Extended Synthesis: Reintegrating Life’s Natural History into Evolution Studies. In E. Serrelli, & N. Gontier (Eds.), Macroevolution. Interdisciplinary Evolution Research (pp. 227-275). Springer International Publishing.
[14]
Gould, S. J. (1990). Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of History. W. W. Norton & Company.
[15]
Gould, S. J., & Eldredge, N. (1977). Punctuated Equilibria: The Tempo and Mode of Evolution Reconsidered. Paleobiology, 3, 115-151.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S0094837300005224
[16]
Hacking, I. (2000). How Inevitable Are the Results of Successful Science? Philosophy of Science, 67, S58-S71. https://doi.org/10.1086/392809
[17]
Huneman, P. (2017). Macroevolution and Microevolution: Issues of Time Scale in Evolutionary Biology. In P. Huneman, & C. Bouton (Eds.), Time of Nature and the Nature of Time (pp. 315-357). Springer International Publishing.
[18]
Mill, J. S. (1843/1930). A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive. Longmans, Green and Co.
[19]
Morgan, C. L. (1923). Emergent Evolution. Williams and Norgate.
[20]
Newman, D. V. (1996). Emergence and Strange Attractors. Philosophy of Science, 63, 245-261. https://doi.org/10.1086/289911
[21]
Rigato, J. (2017). Looking For Emergence in Physics. Phenomenology and Mind, 12, 174-183.
[22]
Silberstein, M., & McGeever, J. (1999). The Search for Ontological Emergence. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 182-200. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9213.00136
[23]
Stefanidou, C., & Skordoulis, C. (2017). Primary Student Teachers’ Understanding of Basic Ideas of Nature of Science: Laws, Theories and Models. Journal of Studies in Education, 7, 127-153.
[24]
Stefanidou, C., Stavrou, D., & Skordoulis, C. (2013). Teaching and Learning the Heuristic Role of Models in Theory Construction in the Context of Nature of Science: The Case of Maxwell’s Vortex Idle Wheel Model. In P. Heering, S. Klassen, & D. Metz (Eds.), Enabling Scientific Understanding through Historical Instruments and Experiments in Formal and Non-Formal Learning Environments (pp.111-126). Flensburg University Press.
[25]
Wosniack, M. E., da Luz, M. G. E., & Schulman, L. S. (2017). Punctuated Equilibrium as an Emergent Process and Its Modified Thermodynamic Characterization. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 412, 113-122. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jtbi.2016.10.008