After a long time, people are still
debating over “Cartesian-like Dualism” (CLD), i.e. towards the separation of
“res-extensa” from “res-cogitans”. Since we suspect that this is due to a
general attraction of mind towards the darkness of metaphysics, we have
investigated the mental origin of this attraction. In human mind, we can
envisage three different functional levels emerging one from the other like in
a Matrioska; the three levels cause the arousal of as many forms of “dualisms”:
1) The 1st-level corresponds to the “Dual-state” of mind, an archetypic dualism
made of Unconscious Mind (UM, the domain of biophysical/biochemical signals)
and Conscious Mind (CM, the domain of thoughts, images and sounds), genetically
committed to reciprocal and fruitful interactions. 2) the 2nd-level
corresponds to “Double-perspective” dualism; it emerges from CM’s splitting
into two opposite perspectives: the 1st-order perspective (1PP) (subjective,
emotional, Self-oriented, etc.) and the 3rd-order perspective (3PP) (rational,
objective, Self-detached, etc.), that are in psychological contraposition.
During individual growth, Ego-sense installs in CM with the illusion of
possessing FW, and dominates 1PP. Conversely, 3PP is typically interested in
scientific argumentations and investigations; so, 3PP confutes 1PP’s
convictions on scien-tific bases (e.g. 1PP’s conviction that the binomial
Ego-FW is real). Yet, on the one hand, 3PP hasn’t got a scientific alternative
to explain “who we really are”, on the other hand, 1PP exhibits a great success
in everyday life cognition. Then, we necessarily step over the dualism of the
3rd-level, “Cartesian-like Dualism” (CLD). The emotional origin of this CLD
holds back 1PP’s trick to claim its supremacy over 3PP.
References
[1]
Aimi, A., Martuzzi, F., & Bignetti, E. (2018). Rational Curves Modelling Psychophysical Tests Data: A Computational Approach Compatible with TBM Cognitive Model. Far East Journal of Mathematical Sciences, 1, 81-108. https://doi.org/10.17654/MS107010081
[2]
Aurobindo, S. (1997). Essays on the Gita. Pondicherry: Sri Aurobindo Ashram Pub. Dept.
[3]
Baars, B. J. (1998). A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
[4]
Baars, B. J. (1997). In the Theater of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195102659.001.1
[5]
Baars, B., & Gage, N. (2019). Fundamentals of Cognitive Neuroscience. Cambridge, MA: Academic Press.
[6]
Baxter, M. G., & Murray, E. A. (2002). The Amygdala and Reward. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3, 563-573. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn875
[7]
Bignetti, E. (2001). Dissacrazione della coscienza. Firenze: Il Valico Edizioni.
[8]
Bignetti, E. (2003). Cervello e mente: Ovvero casualita’ e determinismo. Annals of Veterinary Medicine Faculty, University of Parma, 23, 69-78.
[9]
Bignetti, E. (2004). Consciousness Can Learn But Cannot Decide. Annals of Veterinary Medicine Faculty, 24, 31-52.
[10]
Bignetti, E. (2013). Ego and Free Will: A Virtual Binomial Apt for Cognition. Neural Plasticity and Cognitive Modifiability, Jerusalem, 19-22.
[11]
Bignetti, E. (2014). The Functional Role of Free-Will Illusion in Cognition: The Bignetti Model. Cognitive Systems Research, 31-32, 45-60. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cogsys.2014.04.001
[12]
Bignetti, E. (2015). From Brain to Mind: A Plain Route from Neurobiology to Psychology. Psychology and Cognitive Sciences—Open Journal, 1, 15-25. https://doi.org/10.17140/PCSOJ-1-103
[13]
Bignetti, E. (2017). Which Is Necessary for Cognition, Free Will or Free Will Illusion? Psychology and Cognitive Sciences—Open Journal, 3, 116-122. https://doi.org/10.17140/PCSOJ-3-133
[14]
Bignetti, E. (2019a). Il Binomio “Coscienza-Libero Arbitrio” E’ Un’Illusione Vincente. Amazon.it, Kindle ed. https://www.amazon.it/BINOMIO-COSCIENZA-LIBERO-ARBITRIO-UNILLUSIONE-VINCENTE-ebook/dp/B07NJ285V7
[15]
Bignetti, E. (2019b). May Conscious Mind Give a “Scientific Definition” of Consciousness? Open Journal of Philosophy, 9, 439-451. https://doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2019.94027
[16]
Bignetti, E., Martuzzi, F., & Tartabini, A. (2016). A Psychophysical Approach to Test: The Bignetti Model. Psychology and Cognitive Sciences—Open Journal, 3, 24-35. https://doi.org/10.17140/PCSOJ-3-121
[17]
Bitbol, M., & Luisi, P. L. (2004). Autopoiesis with or without Cognition: Defining Life at Its Edge. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 1, 99-107. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2004.0012
[18]
Blackmore, S. (2002). There Is No Stream of Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9, 17-28.
[19]
Blair, H. T., Schafe, G. E., Bauer, E. P., Rodrigues, S. M., & LeDoux, J. E. (2001). Synaptic Plasticity in the Lateral Amygdala: A Cellular Hypothesis of Fear Conditioning. Learning & Memory (Cold Spring Harbor, N.Y.), 8, 229-242. https://doi.org/10.1101/lm.30901
[20]
Bourgine, P., & Stewart, J. (2004). Autopoiesis and Cognition. Artificial Life, 10, 327-345. https://doi.org/10.1162/1064546041255557
[21]
Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 200-219. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195311105.003.0001
[22]
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
[23]
Chalmers, D. J. (2000). Neural Correlates of Consciousness: Empirical and Conceptual Questions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
[24]
Critchley, H. D., Mathias, C. J., & Dolan, R. J. (2003). Fear Conditioning in Humans: The Influence of Awareness and Autonomic Arousal on Functional Neuroanatomy. Neuron, 33, 653-663. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0896-6273(02)00588-3
[25]
Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness Explained. New York: Penguin Books.
[26]
Gershman, S. J., Monfils, M.-H., Norman, K. A., & Niv, Y. (2017). The Computational Nature of Memory Modification. eLife, 6, e23763. https://doi.org/10.7554/eLife.23763.002
[27]
Gomes, G. (1998). The Timing of Conscious Experience: A Critical Review and Reinterpretation of Libet’s Research. Consciousness & Cognition, 7, 559-595. https://doi.org/10.1006/ccog.1998.0332
[28]
Gonzales, V. C., Lassiter, G. D., Bellezza, F. S., & Lindberg, M. J. (2008). “Save Angels Perhaps”: A Critical Examination of and the Deliberation-without-Attention Effect. Review of General Psychology, 12, 282-296. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0013134
[29]
Internet Sacred Text Archive. https://www.sacred-texts.com/index.htm
[30]
Kandel, E. R. (1996). Cellular Mechanism of Learning and the Biological Basis of Individuality. In E. R. Kandel, J. H. Schwartz, & T. M. Jessel (Eds.), Principles of Neural Sciences (3rd ed., pp. 1009-1031). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall Intl.
[31]
Koch, C. (1999). Biophysics of Computation. New York: Oxford University Press.
[32]
Koch, C., Massimini, M., Boly, M., & Tononi, G. (2016). Neural Correlates of Consciousness: Progress and Problems. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 17, 307-321. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrn.2016.22
[33]
Krishnamurti, J. (1978). Does Free Will Exist? 3rd Conversation 1978. Hampshire: Krishnamurti Foundation Trust Ltd.
[34]
Krishnamurti, J. (1982). The Network of Thought. Hampshire: Krishnamurti Foundation Trust Ltd.
[35]
Krishnamurti, J. (1986). Last Talks at Saanen 1985. Hampshire: Krishnamurti Foundation Trust Ltd.
[36]
Krishnamurti, J., & Bohm, D. (1985). The Ending of Time. London: Victor Gollancz.
[37]
Langland-Hassan, P., & Vicente, A. (2018). Inner Speech, New Voices. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198796640.001.0001
[38]
Libet, B. (1982). Brain Stimulation in the Study of Neuronal Functions for Conscious Sensory Experiences. Human Neurobiology, 1, 235-242.
[39]
Libet, B. (1983). Time of Conscious Intention to Act in Relation to Onset of Cerebral Activity (Readiness Potential): The Unconscious Initiation of a Freely Voluntary Act. Brain, 106, 623-642. https://doi.org/10.1093/brain/106.3.623
[40]
Libet, B. (2005). Mind Time: The Temporal Factor in Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
[41]
Lieberman, A. F., & Amaya-Jackson, L. (2005). Reciprocal Influences of Attachment and Trauma: Using a Dual Lens in the Assessment and Treatment in Infants, Toddlers, and Preschoolers. In L. Berlin, Y. Ziv, L. Amaya-Jackson, & M. T. Greenberg (Eds.), Enhancing Early Attachments: Theory, Research, Intervention, and Policy (pp. 120-126). New York: Guilford Press.
[42]
Liou, C.-H., Hsieh, C.-W., Hsieh, C.-H., Lee, S.-C., Chen, J.-H., & Wang, C.-H. (2007). Correlation between Pineal Activation and Religious Meditation by fMRI. Nature Proceedings, Vol. 1328, 1-18. https://doi.org/10.1038/npre.2007.1328.1
[43]
Lutin, A. (2007). The Limbic Brain. New York: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
[44]
MacLean, P. D. (1970). The Triune Brain, Emotion and Scientific Bias. In F. O. Schmitted (Ed.), The Neurosciences, the 2nd Study Program (pp. 336-349). New York: The Rockefeller Univ. Press.
[45]
Maoz, U., Yaffe, G., Koch, C., & Mudrik, L. (2019). Neural Precursors of Decisions That Matter—An ERP Study of Deliberate and Arbitrary Choice. eLife, 8, e39787. https://doi.org/10.7554/eLife.39787
[46]
Maren, S. (1999). Long-Term Potentiation in the Amygdala: A Mechanism for Emotional Learning and Memory. TINS, 22, 561-567. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0166-2236(99)01465-4
[47]
Masuyama, N., Loo, C. K., & Seera, M. (2018). Personality Affected Robotic Emotional Model with Associative Memory for Human-Robot Interaction. Neurocomputing, 272, 213-225. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neucom.2017.06.069
[48]
Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Boston, MA: Reidel. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-8947-4
[49]
Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1998). The Tree of Knowledge. Boston, MA: Shambala.
[50]
Mullen, J. K. (1983). Understanding and Managing the Temper Tantrum. Child Care Quarterly, 12, 59-70. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01258080
[51]
Munoz, C. (2020). Evolution and Yoga. Hypothesis: From Reptilian to Intuitional Brain. Open Journal of Philosophy, 10, 266-276. https://doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2020.102018
[52]
Nichols, S. (2011). Experimental Philosophy and the Problem of Free Will. Science, 331, 1401-1403. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1192931
[53]
O’Connor, T. (2013). Free Will. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/freewill/
[54]
Pessoa, L. (2017). Do Intelligent Robots Need Emotions? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 21, 817-819. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2017.06.010
[55]
Prescott, A., Alexander, S., Walter, S.-A., Adina, L. R., Thalia, W., & Peter, U. T. (2016). Readiness Potentials Driven by Non-Motoric Processes. Consciousness and Cognition, 39, 38-47. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2015.11.011
[56]
Radhakrishnan, S. (1940). Eastern Religions and Western Thought (2nd ed.). Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
[57]
Schrodinger, E. (1936). Indeterminism and Free Will. Nature, 138, 13-14. https://doi.org/10.1038/138013a0
[58]
Searle, J. R. (1997). The Mystery of Consciousness. The New York Review of Books.
[59]
Shepherd, J. (2012). Free Will and Consciousness: Experimental Studies. Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 915-927. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.concog.2012.03.004
[60]
Spivey, M. (2008). The Continuity of Mind. Oxford Psychology Series, Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press.
[61]
Vicente, A., & Manrique, F. M. (2011). Inner Speech: Nature and Functions. Philosophy Compass, 6, 209-219. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00369.x
[62]
Wegner, D. M. (2002). The Illusion of Conscious Will. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology. https://doi.org/10.7551/mitpress/3650.001.0001
[63]
White, D. G. (2019). The Yoga Sutra of Patanjali: A Biography. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.