Caring for the environment has most often
taken the form of summits. The idea behind summits is that environmental
affairs are global, calling for collective responsibility as well as for
collective action. In this connection, responsibilities have generally been
shared among the various member countries. This is in a bid to reduce the level
of pollution and save our mother earth. In this work, we propose an alternative
way of acting, which is an interpretation of Wittgenstein’s ethical views which
rely mostly on transforming our view of who we are and how we relate to the
world. Our view runs against what we could call the “collective action
paradigm” which usually ends in tu quoque suspicion among the different
stakeholders. When the “save the world task” is shared among
countries, they become suspicious of each other, in such a way that a small
violation of the agreement by one country is considered as a good reason for
others to do the same. In this suspicion game, that sometimes takes other
forms, the real battle, saving the world, is completely forgotten. The ethical
views of Wittgenstein that we reconstruct here have two central elements, the
rejection of psychological subjectivity and the rejection of pragmatism in
ethical affairs that both consider nature as an instrument. Our final aim is
to show that if we consider the most important question of life—what is the
meaning of life?—and give an appropriate answer to it, then we can put an end
to “the darkness of our time1”, which consists in thinking that everything,
including nature, can be subjected to our domination.
References
[1]
Bode, I. (2015). Individual Agency and Policy Change at the United Nations: The People of the United Nations. New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315751436
[2]
Campagna, C., & Guevara D. (2020). Evaluating Climate Change with the Language of the Forms of Life. In G. Henning Brian, & W. Zack (Eds.), Climate Change Ethics and the Non-Human World (pp. 75-89). London: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780429356988-7
[3]
Carter, L. (2019). Indigenous Pacific Approaches to Climate Change: Aotearoa/New Zealand. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-96439-3
[4]
Chauviré, C. (2009). L'immanence de l’ego: Langage et subjectivité chez Wittgenstein. Paris: PUF. https://doi.org/10.3917/cite.038.0025
[5]
Fornès, A. (2017). Sens et éthique: Au coeur du discours, “Wittgenstein à l’hopital”. Nice: Université Cote D’Azur.
[6]
Hadden, J. (2015). Networks in Contention: The Divisive Politics of Climate Change. New York: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316105542
[7]
Hungerford, H. (1994). A Prototype Environmental Education Curriculum for the Middle School (Revised). UNESCO.
[8]
Kengoum, F. (2013). Adaptation and Mitigation Policies in Cameroon: Pathways to Synergy. Bogor: CIFOR.
[9]
Mondoué, R., & Nguemeta, P. (2014). Vérificationnisme et Falsificationnisme, Wittgenstein vainqueur de Popper? Paris: L’Harmattan.
[10]
Morel, B. (2019). Real Option Analysis and Climate Change: A New Framework for Environmental Policy Analysis. Cham: Springer Nature Switzerland AG. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-12061-0
Olson, M. (1978). Logique de l’action collective (M. Levi, Trans.). Paris: PUF.
[13]
Peeters, W. E. (2015). Climate Change and Individual Responsibility: Agency, Moral Disengagement and the Motivational Gap. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.
[14]
Peters, M. (2020). Wittgenstein and the Ethics of Suicide: Homosexuality and Jewish Self-Hatred in Fin de siècle Vienna. In M. Peters (Ed.), An Educational Philosophy and Theory Reader Volume VIII: Wittgenstein, Anti-Foundationalism, Technoscience and Philosophy of Education (pp. 65-79). London: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003017035-4
[15]
Pope Francis (2015). Laudato Si: On Care for Our Comon Home [Encyclical].
[16]
Sarkar, S. (2005). Biodiversity and Environmental Philosophy: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498558
[17]
Sarratt, N. (2012). Ecological Forms of Life: Wittgenstein and Ecolinguistics. Denton, TX: University of North Texas.
[18]
Schonbaumsfeld, G. (2007). A Confusion of the Spheres, Kierkegaard and Wittgenstein on Philosophy and Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199229826.001.0001
[19]
Singer, P. (2010). The Life You Can Save, How to Do Your Part to End World Poverty. New York: Random House Trade Paperbacks.
[20]
Sondergaard Christensen, A.-M. (2019). Boundless Nature: Virtue Ethics, Wittgenstein and Unrestricted Naturalism. In D. M. Benjamin, & K. Oskari (Eds.), Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein (pp. 63-83). New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315181172-4
[21]
Taylor, C. (2019). Our Fellow Creatures. In D. M. Benjamin, & K. Oskari (Eds.), Ethics in the Wake of Wittgenstein (pp. 220-232). New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315181172-11
[22]
Vogler, J. (2016). Climate Change in World Politics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137273413
[23]
Wittgenstein, L. (1974a). Philosophical Grammar (R. Rhees, Ed., & A. Kenny, Trans.) Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
[24]
Wittgenstein, L. (1974b). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus [1922] (D. F. McGuinness, Trans.). London: Routledge.
[25]
Wittgenstein, L. (1998a). Culture and Value, A Selection from the Posthumous Remains (G. V. Wright, Ed., & P. Winch, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell Publishers Ltd.
[26]
Wittgenstein, L. (1998b). Notebooks 1914-1916 [1961] (2nd ed., V. W. M., Ed., & G. E. Anscombe, Trans.) Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.